James stopped at Avignon to see Renouvier. The lat- ter had acquired a warm interest in his young American disciple, many of whose articles he translated and republished in France. In the autumn of 1882 James visited Prague and there made the acquaintance of Ernest Mach, whose later books on sensation and on scientific method so closely approached his own way of thinking; and of Carl Stumpf, with whom he maintained more sympathetic relations than with any other European psychologist. In England, where he settled for a more protracted stay, he became a member of the circle which at that time repre- sented the defense of the empirical tradition against the invading Hegelianism. This circle comprised Shadworth Hodgson, George Croom Robertson, the editor of Mind, James Sully, Les- lie Stephen, Frederick Pollock, Edmund Gur- ney, and Henry Sidgwick. Of these men Hodg- son, an acute intellect but an obscure and prolix writer, exercised a powerful influence on James, who was fond of coupling him with Renouvier as one of the two foremost thinkers of his time. Association with this group confirmed James's inheritance and held him on the whole, despite Continental influences in the tradition of British empiricism. In 1889 he attended the Interna- tional Congress of Physiological Psychology in Paris, and still further extended his European connections. It was here that he first met Theo- dore Flournoy of Geneva, who became one of his lifelong and most intimate friends. Although The Principles of Psychology was not completed until 1890, it began to appear in the form of articles immediately after the proj- ect was undertaken. In "Remarks on Spencer's Definition of Mind as Correspondence" (Jour- nal of Speculative Philosophy, Jan. 1878), he emphasized the essentially active and interested character of the human mind, an emphasis which is the key to his entire thought. In an article entitled, "Are we Automata?" Mind, Jan. 1879), he defended the causal efficacy of con- sciousness against the prevailing scientific ma- terialism; and in "The Spatial Quale" (Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Jan. 1879) he vigor- ously advocated the "nativistic" view, to the ef- fect, namely, that there is an immediate impres- sion (rather than an acquired or inferred idea) of spatial depth. "The Feeling of Effort," con- tributed in 1880 to the Anniversary Memoirs of the Boston Society of Natural History, set forth the author's view of will, in which he rejected the prevailing doctrine of the "feeling of inner- vation"; and adopted a position close to that of Renquvier, according to which will is essential- ly an act of attention by which ideas come into James exclusive possession of consciousness. Two arti- cles of epoch-making importance appeared in Mind in 1884, "On Some Omissions of Intro- spective Psychology" and "What is an Emo- tion?"^ The former presented for the first time James's thorough-going rejection of associa- tionism, his recognition of "feelings of relation," and his insistence on the continuity of the stream of consciousness. The second article contained the so-called "James-Lange Theory" (advanced independently in the same year by James and by the Danish psychologist, C. Lange), to the ef- fect that emotion consists essentially in the visceral and other organic sensations associated with its expression. According to this view the fundamental fact in fear, for example, is the bodily response, internal and external, to danger, the subjective emotion being simply the accom- panying awareness of this response. These were the most novel and influential of the specific doctrines comprised in the Principles, but even taken in the aggregate they do not account for the book's remarkable success. This was due in part to the fact that, owing to the author's erudi- tion and skilful use of citation, it summed up and will always significantly represent the state of the science of psychology at the close of the nine- teenth century. Furthermore, the author broke definitely with the past and with the philosophi- cal alliance, declaring the right and purpose of psychology to enjoy the privileges and immuni- ties of a special science. James was peculiarly qualified to utter such a pronouncement because of his physiological and clinical experience, and because his name was publicly identified with the scientific standpoint and method. Above all, the book was widely read, and will always com- mand attention, because of its style. It revealed the author's genius for catching the elusive and fugitive states of human experience and trans- fixing them with a telling phrase. It was daring in its humor, in its use of colloquial speech, and in its picturesqueness of metaphor and illustra- tion; so that though many doubted whether any- thing so interesting could possibly be scientific, nobody ignored it. The period during which James was compos- ing the Principles was also the period of his greatest activity in an allied but somewhat dubi- ous field of inquiry. Members of the group with which he was associated in London in 1882 were engaged at that time in the organization of the parent Society for Psychical Research. The dis- favor which the subject enjoyed among ortho- dox scientists would have been sufficient to en- list his sympathy. He was loyal to the interests of his friends, notably Edmund Gurney, Henry 593